Dynkin system
A Dynkin system,[1] named after Eugene Dynkin, is a collection of subsets of another universal set {\displaystyle \Omega } satisfying a set of axioms weaker than those of σ-algebra. Dynkin systems are sometimes referred to as λ-systems (Dynkin himself used this term) or d-system.[2] These set families have applications in measure theory and probability.
A major application of λ-systems is the π-λ theorem, see below.
Definition
[edit ]Let {\displaystyle \Omega } be a nonempty set, and let {\displaystyle D} be a collection of subsets of {\displaystyle \Omega } (that is, {\displaystyle D} is a subset of the power set of {\displaystyle \Omega }). Then {\displaystyle D} is a Dynkin system if
- {\displaystyle \Omega \in D;}
- {\displaystyle D} is closed under complements of subsets in supersets: if {\displaystyle A,B\in D} and {\displaystyle A\subseteq B,} then {\displaystyle B\setminus A\in D;}
- {\displaystyle D} is closed under countable increasing unions: if {\displaystyle A_{1}\subseteq A_{2}\subseteq A_{3}\subseteq \cdots } is an increasing sequence[note 1] of sets in {\displaystyle D} then {\displaystyle \bigcup _{n=1}^{\infty }A_{n}\in D.}
It is easy to check[note 2] that any Dynkin system {\displaystyle D} satisfies:
- {\displaystyle \varnothing \in D;}
- {\displaystyle D} is closed under complements in {\displaystyle \Omega }: if {\textstyle A\in D,} then {\displaystyle \Omega \setminus A\in D;}
- Taking {\displaystyle A:=\Omega } shows that {\displaystyle \varnothing \in D.}
- {\displaystyle D} is closed under countable unions of pairwise disjoint sets: if {\displaystyle A_{1},A_{2},A_{3},\ldots } is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets in {\displaystyle D} (meaning that {\displaystyle A_{i}\cap A_{j}=\varnothing } for all {\displaystyle i\neq j}) then {\displaystyle \bigcup _{n=1}^{\infty }A_{n}\in D.}
- To be clear, this property also holds for finite sequences {\displaystyle A_{1},\ldots ,A_{n}} of pairwise disjoint sets (by letting {\displaystyle A_{i}:=\varnothing } for all {\displaystyle i>n}).
Conversely, it is easy to check that a family of sets that satisfy conditions 4-6 is a Dynkin class.[note 3] For this reason, a small group of authors have adopted conditions 4-6 to define a Dynkin system.
An important fact is that any Dynkin system that is also a π-system (that is, closed under finite intersections) is a σ-algebra. This can be verified by noting that conditions 2 and 3 together with closure under finite intersections imply closure under finite unions, which in turn implies closure under countable unions.
Given any collection {\displaystyle {\mathcal {J}}} of subsets of {\displaystyle \Omega ,} there exists a unique Dynkin system denoted {\displaystyle D\{{\mathcal {J}}\}} which is minimal with respect to containing {\displaystyle {\mathcal {J}}.} That is, if {\displaystyle {\tilde {D}}} is any Dynkin system containing {\displaystyle {\mathcal {J}},} then {\displaystyle D\{{\mathcal {J}}\}\subseteq {\tilde {D}}.} {\displaystyle D\{{\mathcal {J}}\}} is called the Dynkin system generated by {\displaystyle {\mathcal {J}}.} For instance, {\displaystyle D\{\varnothing \}=\{\varnothing ,\Omega \}.} For another example, let {\displaystyle \Omega =\{1,2,3,4\}} and {\displaystyle {\mathcal {J}}=\{1\}}; then {\displaystyle D\{{\mathcal {J}}\}=\{\varnothing ,\{1\},\{2,3,4\},\Omega \}.}
Sierpiński–Dynkin's π-λ theorem
[edit ]Sierpiński-Dynkin's π-λ theorem:[3] If {\displaystyle P} is a π-system and {\displaystyle D} is a Dynkin system with {\displaystyle P\subseteq D,} then {\displaystyle \sigma \{P\}\subseteq D.}
In other words, the σ-algebra generated by {\displaystyle P} is contained in {\displaystyle D.} Thus a Dynkin system contains a π-system if and only if it contains the σ-algebra generated by that π-system.
One application of Sierpiński-Dynkin's π-λ theorem is the uniqueness of a measure that evaluates the length of an interval (known as the Lebesgue measure):
Let {\displaystyle (\Omega ,{\mathcal {B}},\ell )} be the unit interval [0,1] with the Lebesgue measure on Borel sets. Let {\displaystyle m} be another measure on {\displaystyle \Omega } satisfying {\displaystyle m[(a,b)]=b-a,} and let {\displaystyle D} be the family of sets {\displaystyle S} such that {\displaystyle m[S]=\ell [S].} Let {\displaystyle I:=\{(a,b),[a,b),(a,b],[a,b]:0<a\leq b<1\},} and observe that {\displaystyle I} is closed under finite intersections, that {\displaystyle I\subseteq D,} and that {\displaystyle {\mathcal {B}}} is the σ-algebra generated by {\displaystyle I.} It may be shown that {\displaystyle D} satisfies the above conditions for a Dynkin-system. From Sierpiński-Dynkin's π-λ Theorem it follows that {\displaystyle D} in fact includes all of {\displaystyle {\mathcal {B}}}, which is equivalent to showing that the Lebesgue measure is unique on {\displaystyle {\mathcal {B}}}.
Application to probability distributions
[edit ]The π-λ theorem motivates the common definition of the probability distribution of a random variable {\displaystyle X:(\Omega ,{\mathcal {F}},\operatorname {P} )\to \mathbb {R} } in terms of its cumulative distribution function. Recall that the cumulative distribution of a random variable is defined as {\displaystyle F_{X}(a)=\operatorname {P} [X\leq a],\qquad a\in \mathbb {R} ,} whereas the seemingly more general law of the variable is the probability measure {\displaystyle {\mathcal {L}}_{X}(B)=\operatorname {P} \left[X^{-1}(B)\right]\quad {\text{ for all }}B\in {\mathcal {B}}(\mathbb {R} ),} where {\displaystyle {\mathcal {B}}(\mathbb {R} )} is the Borel σ-algebra. The random variables {\displaystyle X:(\Omega ,{\mathcal {F}},\operatorname {P} )\to \mathbb {R} } and {\displaystyle Y:({\tilde {\Omega }},{\tilde {\mathcal {F}}},{\tilde {\operatorname {P} }})\to \mathbb {R} } (on two possibly different probability spaces) are equal in distribution (or law), denoted by {\displaystyle X,円{\stackrel {\mathcal {D}}{=}},円Y,} if they have the same cumulative distribution functions; that is, if {\displaystyle F_{X}=F_{Y}.} The motivation for the definition stems from the observation that if {\displaystyle F_{X}=F_{Y},} then that is exactly to say that {\displaystyle {\mathcal {L}}_{X}} and {\displaystyle {\mathcal {L}}_{Y}} agree on the π-system {\displaystyle \{(-\infty ,a]:a\in \mathbb {R} \}} which generates {\displaystyle {\mathcal {B}}(\mathbb {R} ),} and so by the example above: {\displaystyle {\mathcal {L}}_{X}={\mathcal {L}}_{Y}.}
A similar result holds for the joint distribution of a random vector. For example, suppose {\displaystyle X} and {\displaystyle Y} are two random variables defined on the same probability space {\displaystyle (\Omega ,{\mathcal {F}},\operatorname {P} ),} with respectively generated π-systems {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}_{X}} and {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}_{Y}.} The joint cumulative distribution function of {\displaystyle (X,Y)} is {\displaystyle F_{X,Y}(a,b)=\operatorname {P} [X\leq a,Y\leq b]=\operatorname {P} \left[X^{-1}((-\infty ,a])\cap Y^{-1}((-\infty ,b])\right],\quad {\text{ for all }}a,b\in \mathbb {R} .}
However, {\displaystyle A=X^{-1}((-\infty ,a])\in {\mathcal {I}}_{X}} and {\displaystyle B=Y^{-1}((-\infty ,b])\in {\mathcal {I}}_{Y}.} Because {\displaystyle {\mathcal {I}}_{X,Y}=\left\{A\cap B:A\in {\mathcal {I}}_{X},{\text{ and }}B\in {\mathcal {I}}_{Y}\right\}} is a π-system generated by the random pair {\displaystyle (X,Y),} the π-λ theorem is used to show that the joint cumulative distribution function suffices to determine the joint law of {\displaystyle (X,Y).} In other words, {\displaystyle (X,Y)} and {\displaystyle (W,Z)} have the same distribution if and only if they have the same joint cumulative distribution function.
In the theory of stochastic processes, two processes {\displaystyle (X_{t})_{t\in T},(Y_{t})_{t\in T}} are known to be equal in distribution if and only if they agree on all finite-dimensional distributions; that is, for all {\displaystyle t_{1},\ldots ,t_{n}\in T,,円n\in \mathbb {N} ,} {\displaystyle \left(X_{t_{1}},\ldots ,X_{t_{n}}\right),円{\stackrel {\mathcal {D}}{=}},円\left(Y_{t_{1}},\ldots ,Y_{t_{n}}\right).}
The proof of this is another application of the π-λ theorem.[4]
See also
[edit ]- Algebra of sets – Identities and relationships involving sets
- δ-ring – Ring closed under countable intersections
- Field of sets – Algebraic concept in measure theory, also referred to as an algebra of sets
- Monotone class – theoremPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallbackPages displaying short descriptions with no spaces
- π-system – Family of sets closed under intersection
- Ring of sets – Family closed under unions and relative complements
- σ-algebra – Algebraic structure of set algebra
- σ-ideal – Family closed under subsets and countable unions
- σ-ring – Family of sets closed under countable unions
Notes
[edit ]- ^ A sequence of sets {\displaystyle A_{1},A_{2},A_{3},\ldots } is called increasing if {\displaystyle A_{n}\subseteq A_{n+1}} for all {\displaystyle n\geq 1.}
- ^ Assume {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}} satisfies (1), (2), and (3). Proof of (5): Property (5) follows from (1) and (2) by using {\displaystyle B:=\Omega .} The following lemma will be used to prove (6). Lemma: If {\displaystyle A,B\in {\mathcal {D}}} are disjoint then {\displaystyle A\cup B\in {\mathcal {D}}.} Proof of Lemma: {\displaystyle A\cap B=\varnothing } implies {\displaystyle B\subseteq \Omega \setminus A,} where {\displaystyle \Omega \setminus A\subseteq \Omega } by (5). Now (2) implies that {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}} contains {\displaystyle (\Omega \setminus A)\setminus B=\Omega \setminus (A\cup B)} so that (5) guarantees that {\displaystyle A\cup B\in {\mathcal {D}},} which proves the lemma. Proof of (6) Assume that {\displaystyle A_{1},A_{2},A_{3},\ldots } are pairwise disjoint sets in {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}.} For every integer {\displaystyle n>0,} the lemma implies that {\displaystyle D_{n}:=A_{1}\cup \cdots \cup A_{n}\in {\mathcal {D}}} where because {\displaystyle D_{1}\subseteq D_{2}\subseteq D_{3}\subseteq \cdots } is increasing, (3) guarantees that {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}} contains their union {\displaystyle D_{1}\cup D_{2}\cup \cdots =A_{1}\cup A_{2}\cup \cdots ,} as desired. {\displaystyle \blacksquare }
- ^ Assume {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}} satisfies (4), (5), and (6). Proof of (2): If {\displaystyle A,B\in {\mathcal {D}}} satisfy {\displaystyle A\subseteq B} then (5) implies {\displaystyle \Omega \setminus B\in {\mathcal {D}}} and since {\displaystyle (\Omega \setminus B)\cap A=\varnothing ,} (6) implies that {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}} contains {\displaystyle (\Omega \setminus B)\cup A=\Omega \setminus (B\setminus A)} so that finally (4) guarantees that {\displaystyle \Omega \setminus (\Omega \setminus (B\setminus A))=B\setminus A} is in {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}.} Proof of (3): Assume {\displaystyle A_{1}\subseteq A_{2}\subseteq \cdots } is an increasing sequence of subsets in {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}},} let {\displaystyle D_{1}=A_{1},} and let {\displaystyle D_{i}=A_{i}\setminus A_{i-1}} for every {\displaystyle i>1,} where (2) guarantees that {\displaystyle D_{2},D_{3},\ldots } all belong to {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}}.} Since {\displaystyle D_{1},D_{2},D_{3},\ldots } are pairwise disjoint, (6) guarantees that their union {\displaystyle D_{1}\cup D_{2}\cup D_{3}\cup \cdots =A_{1}\cup A_{2}\cup A_{3}\cup \cdots } belongs to {\displaystyle {\mathcal {D}},} which proves (3).{\displaystyle \blacksquare }
References
[edit ]- ^ Dynkin, E., "Foundations of the Theory of Markov Processes", Moscow, 1959
- ^ Aliprantis, Charalambos; Border, Kim C. (2006). Infinite Dimensional Analysis: a Hitchhiker's Guide (Third ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-3-540-29587-7 . Retrieved August 23, 2010.
- ^ Sengupta. "Lectures on measure theory lecture 6: The Dynkin π − λ Theorem" (PDF). Math.lsu. Retrieved 3 January 2023.
- ^ Kallenberg, Foundations Of Modern Probability, p. 48
Further reading
[edit ]- Gut, Allan (2005). Probability: A Graduate Course. Springer Texts in Statistics. New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/b138932. ISBN 0-387-22833-0.
- Billingsley, Patrick (1995). Probability and Measure. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc. ISBN 0-471-00710-2.
- Williams, David (2007). Probability with Martingales. Cambridge University Press. p. 193. ISBN 978-0-521-40605-5.
This article incorporates material from Dynkin system on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.
Families {\displaystyle {\mathcal {F}}} of sets over {\displaystyle \Omega } | ||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Is necessarily true of {\displaystyle {\mathcal {F}}\colon } or, is {\displaystyle {\mathcal {F}}} closed under: |
Directed by {\displaystyle ,円\supseteq } |
{\displaystyle A\cap B} | {\displaystyle A\cup B} | {\displaystyle B\setminus A} | {\displaystyle \Omega \setminus A} | {\displaystyle A_{1}\cap A_{2}\cap \cdots } | {\displaystyle A_{1}\cup A_{2}\cup \cdots } | {\displaystyle \Omega \in {\mathcal {F}}} | {\displaystyle \varnothing \in {\mathcal {F}}} | F.I.P. |
π-system | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | No | No | No | No | No |
Semiring | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | No | No | No | Yes | Never |
Semialgebra (Semifield) | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | No | No | No | Yes | Never |
Monotone class | No | No | No | No | No | only if {\displaystyle A_{i}\searrow } | only if {\displaystyle A_{i}\nearrow } | No | No | No |
λ-system (Dynkin System) | Yes | No | No | only if {\displaystyle A\subseteq B} |
Yes | No | only if {\displaystyle A_{i}\nearrow } or they are disjoint |
Yes | Yes | Never |
Ring (Order theory) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | No | No | No | No |
Ring (Measure theory) | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | No | Yes | Never |
δ-Ring | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | Yes | No | No | Yes | Never |
σ-Ring | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | Yes | Yes | No | Yes | Never |
Algebra (Field) | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | Yes | Yes | Never |
σ-Algebra (σ-Field) | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Never |
Dual ideal | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | Yes | Yes | No | No |
Filter | Yes | Yes | Yes | Never | Never | No | Yes | Yes | {\displaystyle \varnothing \not \in {\mathcal {F}}} | Yes |
Prefilter (Filter base) | Yes | No | No | Never | Never | No | No | No | {\displaystyle \varnothing \not \in {\mathcal {F}}} | Yes |
Filter subbase | No | No | No | Never | Never | No | No | No | {\displaystyle \varnothing \not \in {\mathcal {F}}} | Yes |
Open Topology | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | (even arbitrary {\displaystyle \cup }) |
Yes | Yes | Never |
Closed Topology | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | (even arbitrary {\displaystyle \cap }) |
No | Yes | Yes | Never |
Is necessarily true of {\displaystyle {\mathcal {F}}\colon } or, is {\displaystyle {\mathcal {F}}} closed under: |
directed downward |
finite intersections |
finite unions |
relative complements |
complements in {\displaystyle \Omega } |
countable intersections |
countable unions |
contains {\displaystyle \Omega } | contains {\displaystyle \varnothing } | Finite Intersection Property |
Additionally, a semiring is a π-system where every complement {\displaystyle B\setminus A} is equal to a finite disjoint union of sets in {\displaystyle {\mathcal {F}}.} |