Egalitarian rule
In social choice and operations research, the egalitarian rule (also called the max-min rule or the Rawlsian rule) is a rule saying that, among all possible alternatives, society should pick the alternative which maximizes the minimum utility of all individuals in society. It is a formal mathematical representation of the egalitarian philosophy. It also corresponds to John Rawls' principle of maximizing the welfare of the worst-off individual.[1]
Definition
[edit ]Let {\displaystyle X} be a set of possible `states of the world' or `alternatives'. Society wishes to choose a single state from {\displaystyle X}. For example, in a single-winner election, {\displaystyle X} may represent the set of candidates; in a resource allocation setting, {\displaystyle X} may represent all possible allocations.
Let {\displaystyle I} be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each {\displaystyle i\in I}, let {\displaystyle u_{i}:X\longrightarrow \mathbb {R} } be a utility function , describing the amount of happiness an individual i derives from each possible state.
A social choice rule is a mechanism which uses the data {\displaystyle (u_{i})_{i\in I}} to select some element(s) from {\displaystyle X} which are `best' for society. The question of what 'best' means is the basic question of social choice theory. The egalitarian rule selects an element {\displaystyle x\in X} which maximizes the minimum utility, that is, it solves the following optimization problem:
Leximin rule
[edit ]Often, there are many different states with the same minimum utility. For example, a state with utility profile (0,100,100) has the same minimum value as a state with utility profile (0,0,0). In this case, the egalitarian rule often uses the leximin order, that is: subject to maximizing the smallest utility, it aims to maximize the next-smallest utility; subject to that, maximize the next-smallest utility, and so on.
For example, suppose there are two individuals - Alice and George, and three possible states: state x gives a utility of 2 to Alice and 4 to George; state y gives a utility of 9 to Alice and 1 to George; and state z gives a utility of 1 to Alice and 8 to George. Then state x is leximin-optimal, since its utility profile is (2,4) which is leximin-larger than that of y (9,1) and z (1,8).
The egalitarian rule strengthened with the leximin order is often called the leximin rule, to distinguish it from the simpler max-min rule.
The leximin rule for social choice was introduced by Amartya Sen in 1970,[1] and discussed in depth in many later books.[2] [3] [4] [5] : sub.2.5 [6]
Properties
[edit ]Conditions for Pareto efficiency
[edit ]The leximin rule is Pareto-efficient if the outcomes of every decision are known with certainty. However, by Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem, any leximin function is Pareto-inefficient for a society that must make tradeoffs under uncertainty: There exist situations in which every person in a society would be better-off (ex ante) if they were to take a particular bet, but the leximin rule will reject it (because some person might be made worse off ex post).
Pigou-Dalton property
[edit ]The leximin rule satisfies the Pigou–Dalton principle, that is: if utility is "moved" from an agent with more utility to an agent with less utility, and as a result, the utility-difference between them becomes smaller, then resulting alternative is preferred.
Moreover, the leximin rule is the only social-welfare ordering rule which simultaneously satisfies the following three properties:[5] : 266
- Pareto efficiency;
- Pigou-Dalton principle;
- Independence of common utility pace - if all utilities are transformed by a common monotonically-increasing function, then the ordering of the alternatives remains the same.
Egalitarian resource allocation
[edit ]The egalitarian rule is particularly useful as a rule for fair division. In this setting, the set {\displaystyle X} represents all possible allocations, and the goal is to find an allocation which maximizes the minimum utility, or the leximin vector. This rule has been studied in several contexts:
- Division of a single homogeneous resource;
- Fair subset sum problem;[7]
- Egalitarian cake-cutting;
- Egalitarian item allocation.
- Egalitarian (leximin) bargaining.[8]
See also
[edit ]- Utilitarian rule - a different rule that emphasizes the sum of utilities rather than the smallest utility.
- Proportional-fair rule
- Max-min fair scheduling - max-min fairness in process scheduling.
- Regret (decision theory)
- Wald's maximin model
References
[edit ]- ^ a b Sen, Amartya (2017年02月20日). Collective Choice and Social Welfare. Harvard University Press. doi:10.4159/9780674974616. ISBN 978-0-674-97461-6.
- ^ D'Aspremont, Claude; Gevers, Louis (1977). "Equity and the Informational Basis of Collective Choice". The Review of Economic Studies. 44 (2): 199–209. doi:10.2307/2297061. ISSN 0034-6527. JSTOR 2297061.
- ^ Kolm, Serge-Christophe (2002). Justice and Equity. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-61179-4.
- ^ Moulin, Herve (1991年07月26日). Axioms of Cooperative Decision Making. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42458-5.
- ^ a b Herve Moulin (2004). Fair Division and Collective Welfare. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262134231.
- ^ Bouveret, Sylvain; Lemaître, Michel (2009年02月01日). "Computing leximin-optimal solutions in constraint networks". Artificial Intelligence. 173 (2): 343–364. doi:10.1016/j.artint.2008年10月01日0 . ISSN 0004-3702.
- ^ Nicosia, Gaia; Pacifici, Andrea; Pferschy, Ulrich (2017年03月16日). "Price of Fairness for allocating a bounded resource". European Journal of Operational Research. 257 (3): 933–943. arXiv:1508.05253 . doi:10.1016/j.ejor.2016年08月01日3. ISSN 0377-2217. S2CID 14229329.
- ^ Imai, Haruo (1983). "Individual Monotonicity and Lexicographic Maxmin Solution". Econometrica. 51 (2): 389–401. doi:10.2307/1911997. ISSN 0012-9682. JSTOR 1911997.